By
Mobeen Vaid
July 11,
2018
Introduction
My initial
rebuttal of Scott Kugle’s revisionism[1] on the question of homosexual
relations in Islam was published in July 2016.[2] The central premise of the
article – aside from delineating where Kugle’s revisionism fell victim to
misreadings, misrepresentations, and methodological inconsistencies – was that
Islam’s prohibition of liwāṭ (sodomy) and other same-sex behaviours (i) reflected the obvious
meaning of Quranic passages condemning male-male sexual intercourse and,
therefore, (ii) was not open to reinterpretation (at least not without
employing highly implausible hermeneutics and deviating from matters deemed
“known of the religion by necessity,” and thus definitional of the faith).
Reaction to the piece has been varied. Within mainstream Muslim circles, the response was largely positive. The article was shared online thousands of times within the first week of publication, and notable figures within the Muslim community in America, including Dr. Yasir Qadhi, Dr. Abdullah bin Hamid Ali, and Dr. ShadeeElmasry, among others, disseminated it while offering their own words of support. In certain instances, superlative praise was offered by folks who seem not to have read the article, or to have only read bits and pieces of it and drew conclusions that, ironically, contradicted critical points in the piece (i.e., “this is why homosexuality is ḥarām,” without giving due consideration to the issues of identity construction, desires, and acts that were detailed in the article and are critical to Islam’s valuation of permissibility and prohibition).
Of course,
reacting without reading was not the exclusive preserve of those expressing
approbation. Opprobrium emerged early on from those who regarded the piece as
disparaging the scholarly contributions of Scott Kugle or otherwise “hateful”
to those who self-identify as homosexual. Little proof was furnished to back up
such accusations, though given the politically and emotionally charged state of
the current discourse surrounding homosexuality, it was not an altogether
surprising charge. Others made similarly specious contentions against the
paper, with some respondents online selectively drawing from quotes of Ibn Ḥazm in the piece to portray both the
article and the consensus position in Islam regarding same-sex behavior as
irrational. Had these individuals read the article in its entirety, they would
have realized that it was Kugle who made Ibn Ḥazm an essential piece of his
revisionism project and that my invoking of Ibn Ḥazm was merely to refute Kugle’s
prior depiction.
“Of course, reacting without reading was not
the exclusive preserve of those expressing approbation. Opprobrium emerged
early on from those who regarded the piece as disparaging the scholarly
contributions of Scott Kugle or otherwise ‘hateful’ to those who self-identify
as homosexual. Little proof was furnished to back up such accusations, though
given the politically and emotionally charged state of the current discourse
surrounding homosexuality, it was not an altogether surprising charge.”
Setting
aside these misrepresentations and strawmen, more substantial critiques were
registered as well.[3] It is to these that I turn in the present article. I set
the stage by examining the principal question of Quran interpretation, then
address arguments that appeal to deconstruction or to the diversity of the
Islamic legal tradition as a mechanism for granting homosexual behavior legal
sanction.This is followed by a response to approaches that seek to base
religious normativity on the plurality of historical Muslim practice (the
“Islam as anthropology” approach). Finally, I address the demand for “exact
equivalencies” when treating the prohibition of same-sex acts as analogous to
other forbidden behaviors. After addressing these common objections, I make a
positive case for Islamic sexual ethics in light of the various considerations
that confer moral legitimacy on sexual acts in Islam. Next, following a short
section on pastoral concerns, I conclude with a meditation on the current
stakes in this issue for a Muslim community committed to upholding the
teachings of Islam.
The Book
of God
Examining
the landscape of responses to the original article reveals an unmistakable
fact: every reply of note has expressed itself in terms extrinsic to the Sharīʿa. No one to date has attempted to
defend Kugle’s original hermeneutic. None have stated that Kugle’s allegations
against al-Ṭabarī and others were accurate and honest readings. None have argued
that the Quranic passages condemning “coming with desire unto men instead of
women” can be rendered as referring to anything other than (consensual)
same-sex behaviors, nor has anyone argued that the canonical texts of Islam
support anything other than specifically delineated sexual relationships that
are all necessarily male-female.
In fact,
nary a word has been uttered using arguments indigenous to the sharʿī heritage. One finds a palpable
absence of the Quran in these rejoinders, a total desertion of hadith
literature, and a relinquishing of the legal tradition in toto. To what can we
attribute this omission? It is possible to suggest that we are merely dealing with
a case of oversight. I would submit, however, that what we are encountering is
intentional. Revisionist actors are quickly coming to terms with the fact that
the Islamic tradition has been precise and consistent in its sexual ethics, and
that in this case, the Quranic message is so unequivocal that trying to
continue Kugle’s project is a futile endeavor. To then continue laboring under
the aegis of the Islamic tradition is pointless for those seeking religious
sanction for same-sex acts. Instead, a bricolage of postmodern Western
philosophical arguments is hastily bandied about to pronounce on the Islamic
tradition and deracinate its presiding sexual schema.
The trouble
for revisionists is thus laid bare. Affirming the Quran as divine speech while
concurrently accepting its alleged erroneousness on a subject so vital to the
human experience in the modern world presents an untenable proposition for
revisionist actors. In order to resolve tensions arising from these
incompatible affirmations, it is the Quranic message that is overwritten in the
name of sexual liberty. A Faustian bargain of epic proportions, the logical
outcome of such a negotiation is a minimalist faith with no reference to the
Quran as God’s inerrant word or the prophetic practice as representing the
archetype of how to faithfully live that word. Little thought is given to the
resultant spiritual distance, and even less to the possibility that Islamic
sexual ethics can be both divine and morally defensible.
Deconstructionism
The most
common objection to my original article has been that it inappropriately
invokes the “unanimous consensus” of Islam. The alleged inappropriateness here
is not due to prior disagreement concerning the moral status of homosexual
behavior, but rather because, according to this group, Islam – as a concept –
is not amenable to any objective definition and thus cannot sustain a
“unanimous consensus.” This critique is often nested within a larger
ideological paradigm which asserts that religion contains little to no
meaningful content in and of itself independent of what religious adherents
themselves project onto it. According to this view, religion must remain the
preserve of the open market, and it is only through a constant exchange of
ideas that can be tethered to, or expressed in, religious terms that a
religious meaning can be generated – itself only a singular meaning among a
seemingly endless possibility of meanings. Religion is thus viewed as an empty
vessel, expressed with a vocabulary that has historically acquired meaning
through a process of appropriation by a specific set of powerful social actors.
These actors were said to have entrenched prevailing cultural norms indigenous
to their time and place as expressions of faith to the exclusion of other possibilities
and, in so doing, advancing their subjective wants and desires under the mantle
of religious authority. Because there is no such thing as an objective and (in
principle) unified Islam under this deconstructionist hermeneutic, but instead
only “islams” (each refracting cultural, political, and social subjectivities
in the name of God and faith), maintaining an “Islam” with a singular
definition of any practice or belief is to do little more than engage in
interpretive domineering. Such domineering is said to hegemonically disempower
minoritarian views and subordinate the intellectual contributions of the
disenfranchised to the authority of an allegedly “patriarchal,”
“heteronormative,” and denominationally “chauvinistic” understanding of the faith.
This sort
of deconstructionism has emerged in the past decade as an increasingly favored
method of problematizing normative religious doctrine (at least within academic
Islamic Studies, religious studies, and other secular social science fields in
the Western academy). Its appeal lies in its democratization of interpretive
authority. Figures and groups previously relegated to the margins are now
offered not only a voice, but one on seemingly equal ground with not only
contemporaries, but with predecessors whose positions have carried and continue
to carry immense intellectual weight. Its weakness, however, lies in its
entailments. A true global and indiscriminate hermeneutic of deconstruction
cannot be sustained without leading to complete nihilism.[4] If all “islams”
stand on equal interpretive ground, then no interpretation can be claimed as
better or worse than any other. Indeed, any claim of superior scholarship,
accuracy of meaning, or faithfulness to authorial intent would be dismissed as
mere declarations of power, not truth. Of what use is such an “Islam” at all?
And on what basis would the label of Islam or Muslim hold any meaning?
Moreover,
the irony of such accusations hardly factors into the critique being advanced.
Scott Kugle’s work, to which my piece attends, is entitled Homosexuality in
Islam – not homosexuality in a particular reading of Islam, or a revised
“islam” that can sustain homosexual practice as morally sanctionable. Is Kugle
here not guilty of the same “essentializing” rhetoric?
The
deconstructionist framing also raises the following question: Why is such
reasoning limited to Islam? Feminism, patriarchy, homosexuality, homophobia,
and many other conceptual categories are of contemporary Western provenance,
each with contested definitions and associated strands. Given these
stratifications, should these terms not be viewed as conceptually hollow and
devoid of meaning, in the same way that their advocates claim that the term
Islam itself is?
Finally, it
is worth reflecting here upon yet another irony of the deconstructionist
argument. Revisionist deconstructionism relies upon the view that interpretive
projects are irredeemably prejudiced, with one conspicuous exception: its own.
One must therefore accept that past scholars were “homophobic,” “patriarchal,”
and “bigoted” in any number of ways. Note here that this characterization of
“the past” is applied indiscriminately and in a manner that is entirely
undifferentiated on the basis of time, place, language, denomination, culture,
and any number of variables that would, under normal circumstances, necessarily
result in diversity of thought. However, here we are told to believe that this
past was essentially a monolith in all relevant respects, particularly insofar
as it uncritically normalized allegedly repellent attitudes against constituent
communities and peoples. Moreover, the very revisionists making this claim do
so entirely oblivious to their own prejudices, bigotries, and forms of
intolerance. Accordingly, they can accuse religions of “homophobia” for merely
holding moral instruction concerning licit sexual acts, just as they can accuse
the “premodern world” for instantiating patriarchy in ways that allegedly
rendered female existence pitiable. Is it not at all possible that they are the
ones harboring intolerance? In fact, given the issues at stake along with the
relatively recent emergence of homosexuality as a distinct social identity,
strong ideological pre-commitments are not difficult to locate within
revisionist thought.
Appeals
to Legal and Theological Diversity
In order to
buttress accusations of an inappropriate appeal to consensus, some critics have
been keen to highlight minority sects that differ considerably from normative
Sunni or Twelver Shiite beliefs, including sects that regard some of the five
pillars as inessential practices or endorse a drastically modified version of
them in their own conception of Islam. The idea behind this charge is that much
of what is regarded as essential to the Islamic faith has been subject to
disagreement, and that in reality, my invoking of consensus can only be
maintained if restricted to a narrowly defined Sunnism. This supposed
interpretive latitude, however, only works against these critics: What can
account for such deep denominational variance and interpretive latitude that
fails to register, over the course of fourteen hundred years, a single
denomination permitting same-sex acts? Surely, if denominations were capable of
overcoming said “prejudices” enough to disregard pillars of Islam, then they
were equally capable of overcoming “heteronormativity,” no? It is important to
note here that the legal tradition has registered difference even on the
applicability of ḥadd punishment to same-sex acts, with Ibn Ḥazm and jurists from the Ḥanafī school refusing to admit
sodomy as a ḥadd crime by way of analogy with zinā.[5] Are we then to believe that
agreement over the impermissibility of same-sex acts has been sustained simply
by unreflective prejudice? Is it not at all possible that the unified
prohibition of same-sex acts – upheld universally by all Muslim sects, even
those classified as apostate according to Sunni and Twelver Shiite
dispensations – demonstrates the clarity – and, on this point at least, the
univocality – of Divine Writ?
Islam as
Anthropology
Other
critics have suggested that Islam needs to be understood in light of its lived
historical reality and not the allegedly rigid interpretations upheld by
exegetes and jurists. On this view, the historical practice of Muslims comes to
constitute a new “reading” of Islam (or perhaps, a “true” reading of Islam).
Thus, an “islam” can exist (or, more accurately, has existed) that permits wine
drinking (khamr), fornication and adultery (zinā), and even polytheism (shirk).
Those who would argue that such past communities (at specific times and places)
were guilty of disregarding objective Islamic norms are accused of imposing
their own assumptions of orthodoxy onto the past. Often, this argument is
rooted in the late Shahab Ahmed’s What is Islam?, though such an interpretive
approach fundamentally misunderstands Ahmed’s own stated intentions. In
introducing his work on p. 5, Ahmed states, “In conceptualizing Islam as a
human and historical phenomenon, I am precisely not seeking to tell the reader
what Islam is as a matter of Divine Command, and thus am not seeking to
prescribe how Islam should be followed as the means to existential
salvation.”[6] Ahmed’s stated objective diverges from that of Kugle and other
revisionists who are, in fact, attempting to assert what “Islam” – which they
otherwise deny can be spoken of with any conceptual coherence – says about
homosexuality as a matter of Divine Command. Moreover, even if we are to set
aside Ahmed and deal directly with the substantive assertion of lived
historical expression constituting a new Islam, what would we make of the past
ordinariness of pederastic infatuation directed toward beardless youth (murdān,
sing. amrad)? Would the same folks vesting evidentiary weight in practices that
were widely attested to and registered in the historical record be willing to
argue that pederasty, too, should be made permissible (or, rather, that it was
already permissible given its presence in past societies)? I suspect not.
“Often, this argument is rooted in the late
Shahab Ahmed’s What is Islam?, though such an interpretive approach
fundamentally misunderstands Ahmed’s own stated intentions. In introducing his
work on p. 5, Ahmed states, ‘In conceptualizing Islam as a human and historical
phenomenon, I am precisely not seeking to tell the reader what Islam is as a
matter of Divine Command, and thus am not seeking to prescribe how Islam should
be followed as the means to existential salvation.’[6] “
Question
of Equivalencies
Some
critics have objected to the presence of (allegedly) false equivalencies in my
2016 article. Here, it is said that the paper improperly establishes a parallel
between the sexual stimulation a same-sex attracted individual experiences, on
the one hand, and impulses such as lying, cheating, and stealing, on the other.
Elsewhere it is said that I consign same-sex attracted individuals to a life of
celibacy with a consolation that others too must live with a test of permanent
celibacy, including those who cannot get married due to a shortage of
marriageable partners, poverty, or medical incapacity. Thus, the paper is
described as peddling false analogies and falling victim to an
underappreciation of the qualitative difference between same-sex attraction as
a deep-seated psycho-sexual reality and other tests a person may face. This
argument, like the aforementioned ones cited here, relies on misrepresenting
the essential discursive being employed in the paper while positing a number of
unfounded assumptions.
To begin with, the question must be asked in which context these analogies were raised. Lying, cheating, and stealing, for instance, were all cited in the paper as impulses that appear without consultation, conscious decision, and which can all be conceived of as “natural.” By raising this point, I was not suggesting that eschewing the impulse to cheat is in any way analogous to lifelong celibacy for same-sex attracted individuals. The point was merely that many sins – among which same-sex acts are included – are prompted by impulses that (i) exist in a large number of people, (ii) are ineluctable, (iii) manifest internally with a forceful impulse to be acted upon, and (iv) are nonetheless prohibited in Islamic law. Accordingly, asserting inherency as the requisite basis upon which to rest the moral legitimacy of otherwise sinful acts is not an epistemically valid approach.
Having said
that, the analogy proffered in the piece is an imperfect one in some important
respects: the relative difficulty of abstinence, for example, is not equivalent
to abstaining from the other behaviours mentioned. Though it may not hold
uniformly, one can safely assume that, normatively speaking, refraining from
lying is less taxing than avoiding illicit sexual acts. This much can be
conceded without issue. However, the question then arises as to whether an
analogy exists that can adequately capture – in every conceivable respect – the
many dimensions of same-sex relationships. Heterosexual relationships do not
offer a perfect analogue given the presence of physiological differences
between partners, procreative potential (in many, though not all, instances of
course), and relationship dynamics. Indeed, even male homosexual relationships
differ from female homosexual relationships in significant ways,[7] a fact
which itself could serve to complicate the conflationary term “homosexual.” In
fact, one could posit that no two prohibitions exist that bear an exact
resemblance to each other in all respects. The prohibition against wine
drinking is dissimilar to the prohibition against swine consumption. Likewise,
the prohibition of usury (ribā) differs from the prohibition of trading in risk
or uncertainty (gharar). It would be meaningless, quite clearly, for one to
assert that no two actions can be impermissible unless they are alike in each
and every respect. Such considerations of analogical equivalency, at any rate,
are only relevant where the prohibition of one act is derived from the
prohibition of another, such as in standard cases of legal analogy, or qiyās.
As it stands, however, homosexual behavior is subject to an explicit and
specific prohibition by God in the Quran, one that is in no way derivative of
or dependent upon an analogy to any other prohibition. (Note again that
although the punishment for sodomy has sometimes been derived through analogy
to the punishment for zinā, the prohibition itself stands independently on the
strength of its own evidence and is thus not the result of any scholarly
ijtihād to begin with.)
The demand
for an exact analogy then serves to do little more than distract. It does not
address the substantive concern (namely, the intent of scripture). It does not
offer a moral path for concerned Muslims seeking to abide by God’s command. It
does not even provide comfort to the religiously disinclined struggling with
same-sex desire. Instead, it attempts to discredit Islam’s prohibition of
same-sex behavior by demanding a conceptual impossibility.
A
Criterion for Morally Valid Sexual Relationships
In the
previous section I have attended to the advancing of “naturalness” as an
epistemic basis for determining religious sanctionability, concluding that the
desire to sin often originates ineluctably. Despite the ineluctability of these
desires, however, carrying out sinful actions simply because they were prompted
by naturally occurring desires is not an excuse in the Sharīʿa, as such an excuse could
conceivably be applied to just about any iniquitous act. Accordingly, the
relative preventability of desires bears no consequence in determining moral
right and wrong. However, this raises another question: If the preventability
of sexual desire is not a relevant criterion for judging the morality of sexual
behavior, then on what basis can we establish a sexual ethic? It is possible
here to contend that consent is the only relevant criterion for the moral
permissibility of sexual acts (which reigns as the orthodox presupposition
governing sexual relations in the post-Sexual Revolution West). “
“If the preventability of sexual desire is not
a relevant criterion for judging the morality of sexual behavior, then on what
basis can we establish a sexual ethic? It is possible here to contend that
consent is the only relevant criterion for the moral permissibility of sexual
acts (which reigns as the orthodox presupposition governing sexual relations in
the post-Sexual Revolution West).”
And of
course, consent has its advantages for gay advocates. Sexual predilections held
as disordered or otherwise unnatural in the prevailing sexual schema of the modern
West can be repudiated using the criteria of consent: pedophilic relationships
and bestiality, for instance, are both regarded as providing no meaningful
consent (notwithstanding, of course, the fluidity of consent, the
contestability of child consent,[8] the ambiguity of what constitutes a child,
etc.). Incestuous relationships would certainly present a problem given the
distinct possibility of full consent. In order to maintain the consent
argument, some have qualified consent with provisions related to harm.
According to this reasoning, incestuous relationships are deemed unavoidably
harmful given the increased probability of genetic abnormalities in incestuous
offspring, though recent discussion has problematized this assertion[9]
(Indeed, what “harm” could possibly ensue from an incestuous relationship
between two family members of the same sex, to which genetic considerations
clearly do not apply?). Setting aside these complications, let us proceed for
the moment by accepting the proposed rubric of “consent qualified by harm” as a
justification for the legitimacy of a given sexual practice.
It would
seem we now have a workable sexual ethic that can be brought into conversation
with Islamic sexual norms to then assert the licitness of same-sex relationships.
However, the ethical and moral program upheld by Islam (which is, of course,
the subject at hand) has never viewed consent as the sole criteria for sexual
acts, and much that can be enacted consensually is indisputably prohibited.
Zinā (fornication and adultery), for instance, is prohibited explicitly in the
Quran irrespective of consent. Likewise with physical intimacy short of
intercourse and seclusion between two marriageable persons (khalwa). Indeed,
the elective agreement of two participating parties hardly counts when
determining what is lawful and unlawful sexually in the Sharīʿa.
Understanding
that consent bears little currency in Islamic law, some have argued that the
burdensome nature of lifelong abstinence necessarily calls for a special dispensation
for same-sex attracted individuals, for God does not burden a soul with more
than it can bear. Here, I noted in the paper that many Muslims are de facto
charged with lifelong abstinence. Reasons preventing them from marriage may
include a shortage of marriageable partners (such as the growing phenomenon of
spinsterhood in the West), medical frailty, or poverty, among other reasons.
That these other opposite-sex attracted individuals are theoretically able to
regularize sexual relationships is of little comfort when the practicality of
finding an opposite-sex relationship is virtually non-existent. Now, perhaps it
is true that one can contest whether the two groups being discussed here are
functionally equivalent in every conceivable respect. But the point is not to
present an exact analogy insofar as it is to assert that same-sex attracted
individuals who find themselves unable to marry are not alone in their path of
living a life of celibacy in order to remain faithful to God’s command (It should
be noted that some same-sex attracted individuals have, in fact, entered into
marital relationships with an opposite-sex partner and found fulfillment in
family life, though of course this is not always possible).
In
responding to this parallel, some have suggested that the two groups bear
different psychological tolls. Here, same-sex attracted individuals are
regarded as being inflicted with an emotional tax that opposite-sex attracted
individuals are not. For the former, prohibition is the de facto norm, whereas
for the latter, prohibition is merely a consequence of circumstances.
Additionally, it is said that the causal link between sexual orientation and
lifelong celibacy for the same-sex attracted individual contributes to this
emotional tax (a dynamic which is not the case for their opposite-sex attracted
counterparts). Yet even this contention is not unequivocally defensible, as the
emotional toll for opposite-sex attracted individuals faced with lifelong
celibacy may very well exceed the toll experienced by same-sex attracted
individuals. Moreover, one should not forget the difficulty posed to all people
by the presence of sexual desire. As we read in the Quran, “Beautified for
people is the love of that which they desire—of women and sons, heaped-up sums
of gold and silver, fine branded horses, and cattle and tilled land. That is
the enjoyment of worldly life, but God has with Him the best return.” (ĀlʿImrān, Q 3:14). In a hadith largely
regarded as weak, the Prophet (may God’s peace be upon him) described the
lustful gaze as one of the poisoned arrows of Satan,[10] and in a sound
narration included the one who refuses illicit sex out of his fear of God as
receiving the shade of God’s Throne on the Day of Judgment.[11] The sheer
quantity of verses and prophetic traditions reinforcing sexual restraint is
considerable, and they reflect the difficulty of maintaining an ethic of
chastity.
Exacerbating
the difficulty of the already daunting task of living a chaste and sexually
upright life is a society that has embraced libertinism in the public square.
Never has sexually illicit content been more easily accessible than it is
today. Pornographic content has permeated all media to the point that even
watching sports subjects a person to annual ‘body image’ and ‘swimsuit’
episodes. The most popular television programs display full female nudity[12]
and half of all high school students report having had sexual intercourse
before graduation.[13] 90 percent of young boys and 60 percent of young girls
are exposed to pornography before the age of 18,[14] and a University of
Montreal study intending to explore the sexual attitudes of men in their 20s
who had never viewed porn with those who regularly consumed it ran into a dead
end by reportedly failing to find a single adult male who had never viewed
pornographic material.[15] So ubiquitous is pornographic content on the
internet that it has become virtually inescapable, with some going so far as to
suggest that the internet is “actually for porn.”[16] Indeed, the internet,
television, movies, magazines, advertisements, and the public square are awash
with pornography and the sexualization of women (and, increasingly, of men). In
this context, could not the prohibition of zinā be characterized as implausible
or worthy of reconsideration? Would it not be worth considering, in the name of
empathy, a dispensation given the sheer pervasiveness of sexual content and
claims by some of irrepressibility? Absolutely not. Rather, we should seek to
expand pastoral efforts to help people overcome said challenges and encourage
them to live a morally upright life in the sight of God.
Cynical
readers may construe this point as eliding a critical dimension of this
discussion: the possibility for opposite-sex attracted individuals to enter
into sexual relationships that can somehow mitigate or otherwise quell sexual
urges in this highly sexualized society. Such an argument, however, belies a
rather stark reality as it relates to the power of sexual attraction in a
hypersexualized social and cultural setting. The presence of a sexual outlet
has little to do with porn use, infidelity, and other sexual indiscretions.
Many people in sexual relationships, be it in the form of a marital arrangement
or otherwise, continue to struggle with pornography and related sexual
indiscretions.[17] To then construe a licit sexual outlet as foreclosing on
sexual vice is naïve in the extreme, particularly given the contours of the
modern world.
The
Sexual Ethics of Islam
Conspicuously,
very few critics have attempted to respond to the substantive arguments
concerning the intent of revelation – or at least the normative and
consensus-held interpretation of revelation as it relates to sodomy and other
same-sex acts. In fact, some have gone so far as to concede that general point,
i.e., that the Quran and Sunnah say what they say, and there is little
hermeneutical space to gerrymander new interpretations within. Thus, it is said
that although revelation may unambiguously qualify same-sex acts as illicit and
morally disapproved, the “reasonableness” of revelation must nevertheless be
held up to rational scrutiny. Given this appeal to reasonability, critics have
alleged that intelligent ethical and moral guidelines exist governing sexual
acts in the secular West, but that religion has only “God said so” as its sole
retort. As I have shown above, the reasonableness of arguments offered by
critics – of deconstruction, false equivalencies, naturalness, and consent –
are themselves unable to withstand rational scrutiny. On the other hand, I have
only offered passing justifications in the Kugle article for Islam’s ethics
concerning sexual acts, and will thus attempt to expand on those briefly here.
It should
be understood firstly that the fundamental cause, or ratio legis (ʿilla), of any permission or
prohibition is a definite indicant (dalīl) established by God.[18] In
addition to the text of revelation, scholars have written works extrapolating
wisdoms (ḥikam) inherent in God’s Decree, though it should be noted that these wisdoms
are not the ʿilla of the command or prohibition to which they relate.
The ʿilla is thus the specific decree
that brings a ruling into effect, such as a verse of the Quran or hadith of the
Prophet, whereas any talk of a ḥikma is merely an attempt to understand the possible wisdom behind a
command or prohibition, such as (but not limited to) rationally discernible
benefits or harms. The establishment of the ʿilla of a ruling is separate from,
prior to, and in no way contingent upon our attempts to discern the divine
wisdom, or ḥikma, behind that ruling. It follows from this that disproving a ḥikma does not render the ʿilla inoperative (and therefore also
does not vitiate the ruling). In the case at hand, the prohibition of same-sex
acts stands on proofs in the Quran and Sunnah interdicting these acts. Though
this may be deemed as unsatisfactory by some critics, the very edifice of Islam
is predicated upon the act of submission – i.e., islām – to God. This is not to
say that Islam disregards the question of reasonability, but rather to state
that commands and prohibitions are upheld in spite of one’s ability to
rationalize the basis for said legislation. This rational submission stands in
contrast to the fundamental truths of Islam (i.e., God’s unicity, the
prophethood of Muḥammad, the Afterlife, etc.), which are – and in fact must be –
rationally apprehended in order to count as valid belief. Conversely,
individual commands and prohibitions represent the will of the Lawgiver, and
are laws to be obeyed. The force of a command is not contingent upon our
apprehension of a reason for the command (once we have determined that it is,
in fact, a divine command) nor the wisdom that may have motivated the command,
though we do uphold that God is wise, and that all of His acts, commands, and
prohibitions necessarily embody this wisdom. Thus, though we may find certain
commands amenable to rationalization, subjecting others to similar scrutiny may
prove elusive on account of our limitations which can never entirely encapsulate
God’s wise purposes.
Having said
all of that, the principal wisdom undergirding the prohibition of same-sex acts
is situated within the principle objectives (maqāṣid) of Islamic law. One of the five
principle objectives of Islamic law is the preservation of lineage (nasl) along
with the accompanying family structure predicated upon that lineage.
Accordingly, Islamic law not only prohibits adultery, fornication, sodomy, and
tribadism, but slanderous accusation (qadhf) that casts doubt upon one’s lineage
(common examples include referring to someone as “a child of fornication,” or
bastard – ‘ibn zinā’). The socio-familial guidelines in Islam are thus regarded
as paramount, with the complementarity of the male and female as necessary
constituent elements for any legally sanctioned relationship. The teleology of
the male and female bodies for reproduction and penetrative sexual intercourse
refract this heterosexual paradigm and purpose of preserving progeny. The fact
that reproduction cannot occur in any same-sex arrangement absent artificial
insemination or surrogacy only reinforces the organic biological and
physiological realities of paradigmatically heterosexual acts. God speaks of
this often in the Quran when addressing the matter of creation. A verse in
chapter 49, Sūrat al-Ḥujurāt, reads: “O mankind, indeed We have created you from male and
female and made you peoples and tribes that you may know one another. Indeed,
the most noble of you in the sight of God is the most righteous of you. Indeed,
God is Knowing and Acquainted.” Elsewhere, men and women are said to have been
created from a unified soul, and from them to have produced posterity: “O
mankind, fear your Lord, who created you from one soul and created from it its
mate and dispersed from both of them many men and women. And fear God, through
whom you ask one another, and the wombs. Indeed, God is ever, over you, an
Observer.” (Sūrat al-Nisāʾ, 4:1) By disregarding this cosmic purpose, same-sex acts dishonour this
ordering of creation.
Some critics
have responded to this by observing that Islamic law recognizes sexual pleasure
as a legitimate desire that can be fulfilled in a legally sanctioned
relationship, even if it is carried out in a non-penetrative capacity, or in a
penetrative capacity with the use of contraceptives (minimally ʿazl, or coitus interruptus), between
sterile spouses, and other such scenarios in which sexual activity would not
possess procreative potential. To this, it is important to return to Islam’s
sexual ethics. The principle of nasl that has been explicated imparts not
simply an objective, but a structure that, derivative of that objective,
informs the parameters of legally permitted sexual relationships. This structure is necessarily heterosexual in
paradigm, even if every instance of it is not procreative in purpose or
potential. Same-sex relationships violate this paradigm, while relationships
that bear no procreative potential but nonetheless uphold this socio-familial
ethic and honor the natural male-female complementarity are regarded as not
only permissible, but rewarded by God and praiseworthy. Thus, it is not the
procreative potential that is as critical as the paradigm in which procreation
can plausibly take place (which is necessarily heterosexual) that sets the moral
boundary for Islamic sexual ethics. Viewed within this light, same-sex acts
constitute a direct and blatant violation of the sexual ethics espoused by
Islam while directly infringing on the higher purpose that the law seeks to
establish and promote.
Empathy
and Pastoral Care
A criticism
levelled by several people had to do with the issue of empathy and pastoral
care. Though this is no doubt a relevant and essential component of
conversations concerning same-sex acts and Islam, the purpose behind the paper
was not a pastoral one, and possessing no training or expertise to speak of in
the fields of counselling and pastoral care, it was not an endeavour I wanted
to broach casually. There is a dire need for adequate pastoral approaches
addressing same-sex attracted Muslims, and here I am heartened by some early
work published by a group named Straight Struggle, an online support group for
Muslims who report/experience dominant or exclusive same-sex attractions.
Interested readers are referred to a piece written by the moderator of Straight
Struggle published on MuslimMatters.org entitled, “From a Same-Sex Attracted
Muslim: Between Denial of Reality and Distortion of Religion.”
Concluding
Thoughts
As a final
note on this meditation, I have been asked often about my own motivations for
writing on the subject matter at hand. There is much that can be said here, and
although the following is by no means comprehensive, it is important at least
to outline some of the stakes involved when addressing the reinterpretability
of categorical and consensus-bound prohibitions. Over the better part of the
past century, Muslims in the modern world have found themselves and their
religion subject to considerable scrutiny. Much of this scrutiny has emerged
out of unfavourable political circumstances (colonization, warfare, etc.), and
Muslim groups have worked diligently within this milieu to counteract the
advances of Westernization and its concomitant ideology that conflicts with a
number of essential precepts of the Islamic faith. Though various approaches
have been enacted, a common approach has been that of revisionism, which itself
has taken many shapes. Some revisionists have called for a return to the
positions of the formative period (God’s authorial intent, it is said, is best
understood in this prophetic era) and abandonment of later “accretions.” Others
have encouraged structural overhaul of the tradition, including a casting of
doubt upon prophetic hadith as a category, while yet others have opted for
revising the tradition of legal epistemology to accommodate conclusions that
conform to contemporary norms and values. The most appealing strands of
revisionism in the modern world have largely relied upon a dispensing of the
prophetic tradition and a reengagement with the Quran as the sole source of
revelation. These efforts have proved considerably volatile, and hardly a
command exists except that it has been “revisited” by revisionist scrutiny.
Left untouched by virtually all revisionist efforts has been the status of the
Quran itself. Muslims’ confidence in the historical and scriptural integrity of
the Quran abides, as does the applicability of its commands and prohibitions.
Muslims of all stripes faithfully uphold the Quran as their guide and jealously
defend it against those calling into question whether it should remain
operative as a guide in the modern world. Thus, it can be said that if there is
any unifying component to Islam, it is the Quran and a full affirmation of its
status as direct divine revelation.
Any acceptance
of revisionism that permits same-sex acts will necessarily result in a
diminishing of said unassailability. Though some revisionists might insist that
resourceful and otherwise imaginative “interpretations” can be marshalled in
the service of this effort, at times such efforts strain the bounds of minimal
plausibility, even for the ideologically predisposed. Construing unambiguous
scripture stating, “Verily you come with desire unto men instead of women,” as
offering no comment at all on (consensual) same-sex acts is simply too
far-fetched for most people, and over time a reconfiguration of this nature
will damage the last remaining edifice tying the umma together, i.e., the
incontrovertible and unquestioned commitment to the Quran as the source of truth
and guidance. Diluted reform denominations will be the only refuge for folks
admitting this re-reading, and over time other tenets will follow suit.
Although
academics normatively profess ideological neutrality, we all write from a
particular position. Readers will not find mine difficult to detect. I profess
Islam, and write as a Muslim concerned about the vitality of his own faith in
the contemporary West. Despite this concern, I am confident in the plan of God
to whom we all have to answer. As I have gone to great pains to demonstrate,
the Lot narrative in the Quran is clear, unambiguous, and categorical. Those
willing to disregard revelation in order to accommodate homosexual acts as
morally valid despite this, then to you is your dīn, and to me is mine.
And God
Knows Best.
-----
[1] Kugle’s original Homosexuality in Islam is
available here: https://oneworld-publications.com/homosexuality-in-islam.html
In it, Scott Kugle has argued that the sources of Islamic normativity can
plausibly be read as permitting homosexual behaviors and relationships. This
was a novel project as revisionist projects preceding Kugle questioned the
authority of the Islamic tradition, whereas Kugle attempted to show how the
tradition could actually be rendered to support revisionist outcomes. My
response to his paper contended that the project was a failed one. This
contention was buttressed by an examination of Kugle’s many methodological
inconsistencies, misreadings of the tradition, and misrepresentations of al-Ṭabarī and others. Subsequent
responses to my paper by revisionists abandoned Kugle’s project, presumably
because they recognized that there is no way that the sources of Islamic
normativity could support their values. These responses are examined in this
paper.
[2] See
MobeenVaid, “Can Islam Accommodate Homosexual Acts? Qur’anic Revisionism and
the Case of Scott Kugle,” at:
https://muslimmatters.org/2016/07/11/can-islam-accommodate-homosexual-acts-quranic-revisionism-and-the-case-of-scott-kugle/
republished in American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences (AJISS) 34, no. 3
(2017).
[3] The
following piece by Junaid Jahangir and Hussein Abdullatif has only recently
come to my attention:
https://www.irannamag.com/en/article/homosexuality-emerging-new-battleground-islam/
– a full response to this would require a lengthier treatment than this article
offers, and due to a variety of constraints, it is not in scope for the current
article. Perhaps I will take the time in a future article to address fully the
range of claims within it, God Willing.Junaid Jahangir & Hussein
AbdullatifJunaid Jahangir & Hussein Abdullatif
[4] On
postmodern relativity, readers are encouraged to review the transcript of
Graham Leonard’s “The Tyranny of Subjectivity.” See Graham Leonard, “The
Tyranny of Subjectivity,” Vital Speeches of the Day 54, no. 2 (1987), p. 50.
[5] See,
for instance, MuḥammadShāhKashmīrī and Aḥmad ʿAlī al-Sahāranpūrī, Jāmiʿ al-Tirmidhī al-muḥashshā (Karachi: QadīmīKutubkhāne, n.d.), 338.
[6] See
Shahab Ahmed, What Is Islam?: the Importance of Being Islamic. (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 2017), 5. Emphasis mine.
[7] See
for instance “A New Classification System for Lesbians: The Dyke Diagnostic
Manual,” Journal of Lesbian Studies, 14:4 (2010), 401-414, DOI: 10.1080/10894161003677133.
This is but one dimension in which differences between male and female
homosexuality have been observed, though many others exist.
[8] A
particularly trenchant treatment of the subject can be found in Max More’s “A
Self-Critique of Youthful Folly: On Sex, Coercion, and the Age of Consent.” See
Max More, “A Self-Critique of Youthful Folly: On Sex, Coercion, and the Age of
Consent,” Personal Perspectives, no. 26. London, 2011.
[9] See
Eugene Volokh. “Adult Incest and the Law.” The Washington Post, 23 Jan. 2015.
Also see Brett H. Mcdonnell, “Is Incest Next?” Cardozo Women’s Law Journal,
vol. 10, no. 2, Feb. 2004, doi:10.2139/ssrn.442520.
[10]
Among the scholars who are reported to have classified it as weak are
al-Mundhirī (d. 656/1258), al-Haythamī (d. 807/1404), and al-Albānī (d.
1419/1999). See:
http://fatwa.islamweb.net/fatwa/index.php?page=showfatwa&Option=
FatwaId&Id=253867 for a brief discussion of this ḥadīth.
[11] See
Muḥammad b. Ismāʿīl al-Bukhārī, Ṣaḥīḥ al-Bukhārī, 1 ed. (Damascus: Dār
Ibn Kathīr, 1423/2002), no. 6421.
[12] The
portrayal of nudity and sexual intercourse on television has been characterized
by some as an “epidemic.” See
http://entertainment.time.com/2013/06/10/is-there-an-epidemic-of-nudity-on-primetime-tv/
as well as a study by the Parents Television Council (PTC) reporting a 6,300
percent increase in depictions of full frontal nudity on prime time television
stations between the years 2010 and 2011. The PTC study can be accessed here:
http://www.parentstv.org/PTC/publications/reports/NudityStudy_2012/2012_NudityMiniStudy.pdf
[13] See
Cavazos-Rehg PA, Krauss MJ, Spitznagel EL, Schootman M, Bucholz KK, Peipert JF,
et al. “Age of sexual debut among US adolescents.” Contraception.
2009;80(2):158–162.
[14] See
Elwood D. Watson, “Pornography Addiction Among Men Is On The Rise.” The
Huffington Post, 10 Oct. 2014.
[15]
Jonathan Liew, “All Men Watch Porn, Scientists Find.” The Telegraph, Telegraph
Media Group, 2 Dec. 2009.
[16]
Julie Ruvolo, “The Internet Is For Porn (So Let’s Talk About It).” Forbes,
Forbes Magazine, 7 Aug. 2012.
[17] A
recent study on the effect of pornographic consumption on marital stability
reported too few men giving up the genre to arrive at reliable conclusions
concerning the possible benefit to marital stability that abandoning
pornographic viewing could render for men. (By way of comparison, women who had
managed to abandon the use of porn reported being only one-third as likely to
divorce as those who continued the habit.) See S. L. Perry & C. Schleifer
(2017). “Till porn do us part? A longitudinal examination of pornography use
and divorce.” Journal of Sex Research. Meanwhile, other studies report a rise
in pornographic addictions, with an addict defined as someone who spends more
than eleven hours viewing pornography weekly. See “Porn Addiction Stats.” Porn
Addiction Stats – How Many People Are Really Addicted to Pornography? –
TechAddiction.
[18] See
Nabil Shehaby, “ʿIlla and Qiyās in Early Islamic Legal Theory.” Journal of the American Oriental
Society, vol. 102, no. 1, 1982, p. 27., doi:10.2307/601109.
Original
Headline: Can Islam Accommodate Homosexual Acts? Meditations on the Past Two
Years
Source: The Maydan
URL: https://newageislam.com/books-documents/homosexual-behaviour-subject-explicit-specific/d/122365
New
Age Islam, Islam Online, Islamic Website, African
Muslim News, Arab
World News, South
Asia News, Indian
Muslim News, World
Muslim News, Women
in Islam, Islamic
Feminism, Arab
Women, Women
In Arab, Islamophobia
in America, Muslim
Women in West, Islam
Women and Feminism